Jump to content

NC (complexity)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 132.77.4.43 (talk) at 16:20, 18 March 2012. The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

{{unsolved|computer science|Is Failed to parse (unknown function "\math"): {\displaystyle \textbf{P} \subset \textbf{NC} <\math> ?}} In [[computational complexity theory|complexity theory]], the class '''NC''' (for "Nick's Class") is the set of [[decision problem]]s decidable in [[polylogarithmic time]] on a [[parallel computing|parallel computer]] with a polynomial number of processors. In other words, a problem is in '''NC''' if there exist constants ''c'' and ''k'' such that it can be solved in time [[Big O notation|''O'']](log<sup>''c''</sup>&nbsp;''n'') using [[Big O notation|''O'']](''n''<sup>''k''</sup>) parallel processors. [[Stephen Cook]] coined the name "Nick's class" after [[Nick Pippenger]], who had done extensive research on circuits with polylogarithmic depth and polynomial size. Just as the class '''[[P (complexity)|P]]''' can be thought of as the tractable problems ([[Cobham's thesis]]), so '''NC''' can be thought of as the problems that can be efficiently solved on a parallel computer. It is unknown whether '''P''' is contained in '''NC''', but most researchers suspect this to be false, meaning that there are probably some tractable problems which are "inherently sequential" and cannot significantly be sped up by using parallelism. Just as the class '''[[NP-Complete]]''' can be thought of as "probably intractable", so the class '''[[P-Complete]]''', when using '''NC''' reductions, can be thought of as "probably not parallelizable" or "probably inherently sequential". The parallel computer in the definition can be assumed to be a ''parallel, random-access machine'' ([[parallel random access machine|PRAM]]). That is a parallel computer with a central pool of memory, and any processor can access any bit of memory in constant time. The definition of '''NC''' is not affected by the choice of how the PRAM handles simultaneous access to a single bit by more than one processor. It can be CRCW, CREW, or EREW. See [[parallel random access machine|PRAM]] for descriptions of those models. Equivalently, '''NC''' can be defined as those decision problems decidable by a [[Boolean circuit|uniform Boolean circuit]] (which can be calculated from the length of the input) with [[polylogarithmic]] depth and a polynomial number of gates. [[RNC (complexity)|RNC]] is a class extending NC with access to randomness. == Problems in NC == As with '''P''', by a slight abuse of language, one might classify function problems and search problems as being in '''NC'''. '''NC''' is known to include many problems, including * Integer addition, multiplication and division; * Matrix multiplication, determinant, inverse, rank; * Polynomial GCD, by a reduction to linear algebra using [[Sylvester matrix]] (it is open whether integer GCD is in NC); * Finding a maximal matching. Often algorithms for those problems had to be separately invented and could not be naively adapted from well-known algorithms - Gaussian elimination and Euclidean algorithm rely on operations performed in sequence. One might contrast [[ripple carry adder]] with a [[carry-lookahead adder]]. == The NC Hierarchy == '''NC'''<sup>''i''</sup> is the class of decision problems decidable by uniform boolean circuits with a polynomial number of gates and depth ''O''(log<sup>''i''</sup>&nbsp;''n''), or the class of decision problems solvable in time ''O''(log<sup>''i''</sup>&nbsp;''n'') on a parallel computer with a polynomial number of processors. Clearly, we have :<math>\textbf{NC}^1 \subseteq \textbf{NC}^2 \subseteq \cdots \subseteq \textbf{NC}^i \subseteq \cdots \textbf{NC}}

which forms the NC-hierarchy.

We can relate the NC classes to the space classes L and NL. From Papadimitriou 1994, Theorem 16.1:

Similarly, we have that NC is equivalent to the problems solvable on an alternating Turing machine with space and alternations.[1]

Open problem: Is NC proper?

One major open question in complexity theory is whether or not every containment in the NC hierarchy is proper. It was observed by Papadimitriou that, if NCi = NCi+1 for some i, then NCi = NCj for all j ≥ i, and as a result, NCi = NC. This observation is known as NC-hierarchy collapse because even a single equality in the chain of containments

implies that the entire NC hierarchy "collapses" down to some level i. Thus, there are 2 possibilities:

It is widely believed that (1) is the case, although no proof as to the truth of either statement has yet been discovered.

Barrington's theorem

A branching program with n variables of width k and length m consists of a sequence of m instructions. Each of the instructions is a tuple (i, p, q) where i is the index of variable to check (1 ≤ in), and p and q are functions from {1,2,...,k} to {1,2,...,k}. The program initially starts in state 1, and each instruction (i, p, q) changes the state from x to p(x) or q(x), depending on whether i-th variable is 0 or 1.

A family of branching programs consists of a branching program with n variables for each n.

It's easy to show that every language L on {0,1} can be decided using a family of branching programs of width 4 and exponential length, or using a family of exponential width and linear length.

Every regular language on {0,1} can be recognized with a family of branching programs of constant width and linear number of instructions (since a DFA can be converted to a branching program).

Barrington's theorem[2] says that the class of languages recognized with a family of branching programs of width 5 and polynomial length is exactly nonuniform NC1. The proof uses nonsolvability of symmetric group S5.

The theorem is rather surprising. It implies that majority function can be computed with a family of branching programs of constant width and polynomial size, while intuition might suggest that to achieve polynomial size, one needs linear number of states.

Proof of Barrington's theorem

A branching program of constant width and polynomial size can be easily converted (via divide-and-conquer) to a circuit in NC1.

Conversely, suppose a circuit in NC1 is given. Without loss of generality, assume it uses only AND and NOT gates.

Lemma 1: If there exists a branching program that sometimes works as permutation P and sometimes as Q, by right-multiplying permutations in first instruction by , and in last instruction left-multiplying by , we can make a circuit of the same length that behaves as or respectively.

Call a branching program -computing a circuit if it works as identity when C's output is 0, and as when C's output is 1.

As a consequence of lemma 1 and the fact that all cycles of length 5 are conjugate, for any two 5-cycles if there exists a branching program -computing a circuit C, then there exists a branching program -computing the circuit C, of the same length.

Lemma 2: There exists 5-cycles such that their commutator is a 5-cycle. For example, , .

We will now prove Barrington's theorem by induction.

Assume that for all subcircuits of and 5-cycles , there exists a branching program -computing . We will show that for all 5-cycles , there exists a branching program -computing .

  • If the circuit outputs , the branching program has one instruction checking and outputting identity or respectively.
  • If the circuit outputs , where is a different circuit. Create a branching program -computing , and multiply output of the program (using lemma 1) by to get a branching program outputting or , i.e. -computing .
  • If the circuit outputs , join the branching programs that -compute D, -compute C,-compute D, -compute C. If one of the circuits outputs 0, the resulting program will be identity; if both circuits output 1, the resulting program will work as . In other words, we get a program -computing . Because and are two 5-cycles, they are conjugate, and there exists a program -computing .

The size of the branching program is at most , where d is the depth of the circuit. If the circuit has logarithmic depth, the branching program has polynomial length.

References

  1. ^ S. Bellantoni and I. Oitavem (2004). "Separating NC along the delta axis". Theoretical Computer Science. 318: 57–78.
  2. ^ D. A. Barrington. Bounded-Width Polynomial-Size Branching Programs Recognize Exactly Those Languages in NC1